Deflating the Illusion of Mathematical Miracles in Nature
Written on
Chapter 1: The Paradox of Mathematics in Nature
In a thought-provoking interview, theoretical physicist Paul Davies expressed the common scientific bewilderment surrounding the connection between mathematics and the physical universe. He noted that the complexities of our everyday experiences might lead us to think that understanding the world is an impossible task. However, underneath that intricate surface lies an astonishingly orderly mathematical framework that demands significant effort to uncover. This hidden structure can be likened to a coded message; we have grown accustomed to utilizing mathematics to explain various phenomena—be it calculating spacecraft trajectories or analyzing laser properties. People often take these mathematical applications for granted.
Yet, it is truly extraordinary that mathematics, a product of human ingenuity, finds relevance in the fundamental workings of nature, which continuously unfold around us. These mathematical principles are not limited to what we encounter in daily life; rather, they emerge from intricate experiments conducted under unusual conditions that would not typically occur outside laboratory settings. Through the manipulation of complex equations, we gain insights into the universe's underlying processes.
There exists a cohesive connection among various phenomena, suggesting that the universe is not merely a random collection of objects, but a dynamic system governed by consistent rules. We refer to these rules as "the laws of physics" or "the laws of nature." One of the most profound inquiries we can make is regarding the origin of these laws and whether they must exist in their current form.
This enigma regarding the effectiveness of mathematics can be traced back to ancient Greek philosophers who first identified mathematical harmonies in music and geometry, leading them to conclude that nature embodies an ordered cosmos infused with purpose.
Galileo famously asserted, "The laws of Nature are written in the language of mathematics…the symbols are triangles, circles and other geometrical figures, without whose help it is impossible to comprehend a single word." Similarly, physicist Eugene Wigner articulated similar astonishment in his influential 1960 article titled "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences."
Chapter 2: Tracing the Roots of Arithmetic
To delve into this mystery, let’s examine a fundamental aspect of mathematics: the operations of addition and subtraction. Mathematics begins with our shared experiences, which are then articulated through concepts labeled by words in our native languages.
Consider the etymology of terms like "add," "increase," and "subtract." The word "add" originates from the Latin "addere," which means to place towards (ad = toward + dere = to put). The core idea involves the concept of allocation—setting something aside to contribute to something else, much like creating a pile of dirt by adding shovelfuls.
Meanwhile, "increase" comes from the Latin "increscere," meaning "to grow." This root evokes the image of the moon's phases, which may appear to grow or shrink as the light varies based on its position relative to Earth. The term "subtract" is derived from "subtractus," indicating the action of drawing away or undermining.
These ordinary concepts, associated with terms in natural language, correspond to tangible, often human-centric experiences. Yet, the mystery that Paul Davies highlights is not simply that natural processes conform to our intuitive notions. Instead, mathematicians abstract these intuitive concepts, distancing them from human-centric perspectives.
Chapter 3: The Technical Foundations of Mathematics
The mathematical notion of addition represents a function that produces a specific output from given input values, following the principles of set theory. A function serves as a rule that maps elements from a set of possible inputs (the domain) to a set of allowable outputs (the codomain).
This formalization of addition replaces the experiential idea of combining physical objects with a technical concept grounded in set theory. The term "set" itself has an intriguing origin, derived from the Latin "secta," meaning a religious faction, later influenced by the verb "set," which implies placement.
If we consider the distinction between two abstract sets—like a collection of apples and the total of those apples—we might liken it to the disagreements among different religious sects. However, neither the original context nor the notion of placing something in a specific location informs the mathematical definition of adding sets. Thus, there is a significant divide between natural and artificial languages, crucial for understanding the mystery of mathematics' effectiveness.
The perplexing question arises: Why do natural phenomena adhere to the rules of addition and subtraction? Why does the act of combining two groups of apples yield a consistent mathematical result? In reality, items like apples are not truly added or subtracted; these mathematical operations pertain to abstract concepts rather than tangible objects.
The operations of arithmetic exist within an artificial language that refers to logical functions, devoid of any inherent connection to the empirical world. Consequently, the efficacy of mathematics in modeling reality raises further questions about the nature of our understanding and the frameworks we construct.
Chapter 4: The Dichotomy of Mathematical Proof
Perhaps the apparent harmony between mathematics and the natural world is an illusion. Consider the distinction between empirical and mathematical proofs; real-world evidence is often indirect and open to multiple interpretations, whereas mathematical proofs rely on axioms and definitions.
This disconnection between mathematics and reality underscores the nature of mathematical reasoning, which is often divorced from the complexities of the physical world. The operations of arithmetic, for instance, exist as abstract constructs rather than reflections of tangible reality.
Ultimately, while mathematical tools are immensely helpful in organizing our understanding of nature, they may not necessarily reveal profound truths about the universe. Our knowledge represents a human-centric interpretation of an indifferent reality, shaped by our evolutionary and cognitive frameworks.
Chapter 5: The Hierarchy of Abstractions
As we explore the levels of abstraction in mathematics, we note the difference between individual items and the properties we ascribe to them. For instance, while no two apples are identical, we categorize them as "apples" based on shared characteristics.
At a higher level, the concept of numbers abstracts from the unique features of various categories, allowing us to apply arithmetic rules universally. This hierarchy of abstraction raises further questions about why our mathematical frameworks are so effective in elucidating the natural world.
Paul Davies suggests that scientists "decrypt" the order of nature, implying that an inherent structure exists for us to uncover. However, this notion also invites skepticism regarding the relationship between our mathematical models and the underlying reality.
In conclusion, while mathematical games serve as useful instruments for navigating our understanding of nature, they do not guarantee a direct connection to the universe's fundamental truths. Our knowledge is shaped by our perceptions and experiences, making it inherently subjective.